To summarise:
* his conception of the Veil of Ignorance is not coherent;
* his assertion that people behind said veil would agree is wrong;
* his assumption that all are risk-averse is wrong;
* his idea that socio-economic stuff should be mixed in with justice is wrong;
* the comparisons that he so casually asserts can be made between radically different societies cannot be made.
Now we come to chapter 3. I find The two principles of justice, however, seem to be a reasonable proposal. In fact, I should like to show that these principles are everyone's best reply, so to speak, to the corresponding demands of the others. In this sense, the choice of this conception of justice is the unique solution to the problem set by the original position. He needs this; because he wants an unique solution. Framed the way he does, though, he will not get an unique solution. This is because, unlike Hobbes, his solution is not constructive. Instead, his solution consists of him pulling out his favoured principles and saying "now I am going to show you a list of other things and I think you'll agree mine is best" (I am not joking). Whereas Hobbes proceeds, logically, step by step, deducing everything he says from what has gone before (as an aside, Hobbes is wrong, because the correct solution - or so I say - is not an unlimited Sovereign; but Hobbes argument is good, and most people will not be able to point at the flaw. Whereas Rawls is riddled with obvious errors. Also, Hobbes language (stemming, I suspect, from his erudition) is vastly superior).
Quoth Rawls: I shall simply take as given a short list of traditional conceptions of justice, for example those discussed in the first chapter, together with a few other possibilities suggested by the two principles of justice. I then assume that the parties are presented with this list and required to agree unanimously that one conception is the best among those enumerated. We may suppose that this decision is arrived at by making a series of comparisons in pairs. Thus the two principles would be shown to be preferable once all agree that they are to be chosen over each of the other alternatives... Now admittedly this is an unsatisfactory way to proceed. It would be better if we could define necessary and sufficient conditions for a uniquely best conception of justice and then exhibit a conception that fulfilled these conditions. Eventually one may be able to do this. For the time being, however, I do not see how to avoid rough and ready methods... For the present, no attempt is made to deal with the general problem of the best solution. I limit the argument throughout to the weaker contention that the two principles would be chosen from the conceptions of justice on the following list.
He then proceeds to list his "two principles" vs various versions of utilitarianism. Since utilitarianism doesn't work (everyone knows this, don't they? I don't have to prove it), this gives him an easy win. But he has carefully excluded just-his-first-principle from the comparison.
That gets me to the end of Chapter three, and of Part I entirely. Woot.
Update: Fifty Shades of Gray
John Gray, who I'll get to in a moment, notices some of the problems with Rawls, in his Enlightenment's Wake. In particular, in Agonistic Liberalism, he points out that Rawls' work is anti-political (p 76 in the Routledge paperback edition). I think this is true, in the sense that Rawls wants, not rule by philosopher-kings, but rules devised by same; and in this way he has fallen into the trap that Plato left him. Gray's contention is that Rawls expects too much: that he wants to deduce too much, he expects too much to be determined from his principles. And as I said above, he can't have this. Gray concludes that politics will have to solve conflicts of rights, whereas Rawls waves the conflicts away (p 72, "contoured").
Update: An Approach to Teaching Rawls And Income Inequality
[2023/05] Michael Munger offers some empirical observations as to whether people would indeed choose as Rawls says they would.
Refs
* Rawls’ Problem of Stability - Michael Huemer.
* WHAT ARE THE MODERN CLASSICS? THE BARUCH POLL OF GREAT PHILOSOPHY IN THE TWENTIETH CENTURY finds Rawls at #3. FFS.
* NotebookLM discusses this (probably private to me).
Good. Now you can write about something more interesting (to me).
ReplyDeleteNo defence of Rawls? I'd have thought he'd be your cup of tea.
ReplyDeleteMight I suggest a more fruitful line of investigation (time passing) for you?
ReplyDeletehttps://www.youtube.com/watch?v=Tu0mzwM9yP4
I am content to say that I did not know John R. from Lou before your essays, and I am largely allergic to philosophy in general and political philosophy in particular. From Plato to Rawls it seems political philosophers talk mostly of an imaginary world almost nothing like the real one. His veil of ignorance idea strikes me as ridiculous. Humans are acutely aware of status and compete constantly for it.
ReplyDeleteNo wonder Harvard appointed a UCal San Diego Provost as Rawl's anointed successor with Al Gore's blessings
ReplyDeleteI know I’m late to the party, so if you’ve already moved on, please ignore. (I'm lumping a reply to all 3 Rawls posts into this one.)
ReplyDelete> “[Rawls] assumes that everyone is completely risk-averse…This is false, so large swathes of the work become invalid.” - WMC
This is an uncharitable interpretation at best. Even if you feel that people would choose a society where they could be very poor/wealthy over a more equitable society (from the VoI), it does not follow that his arguments are wrong. It seems as though you’re trying to argue that some people are unreasonable, therefore Rawls is wrong that its more reasonable to aim for an equitable society. Now this doesn’t mean Rawls is right, but your line of reasoning to show Rawls is wrong is toothless. But perhaps I’m being uncharitable in my interpretation. In my defence, you haven’t provided much other than saying this and that is wrong.
Also, you seem to focus primarily on the VoI but Rawls defends his two principles from two arguments: (1) the official argument (original position, VoI) and (2) the moral arbitrariness argument; I think you ignore the latter. Perhaps because you don’t like it (or didn’t read it), but I think it’s important.
> “Unfortunately, he decides to mix in "social justice" or "economic justice"” – WMC
This is why the moral arbitrariness argument and his differentiation between moral desert and entitlements are important.
In a meritocratic view, people DESERVE what they earn in a free/fair market. In Rawls’ view, people are ENTITLED to what they earn in a free/fair market. However, the acquisition of their talents and how society values their talents are morally arbitrary and therefore we cannot make desert claims. Where the “justice” comes into it is in how we should shape institutions such that the entitlements fairly reflect the moral arbitrariness of the acquisition and valuation of talents.
As Rawls says, “The natural distribution [of talents] is neither just nor unjust; nor is it unjust that persons are born into society at some particular position. These are simply natural facts. What is just and unjust is the way that institutions deal with these facts.”
> “except it is the how-to-divide-a-fixed-pie fallacy. In the real world, nothing is so static” – WMC
Rawls doesn’t do this. He agrees that if a law/policy creates massive wealth at the top but also improves the least advantage group by a lesser amount (directly or indirectly), it still satisfies the Difference Principle. However, if there’s another policy that improves the wealth at the top by less but improves the least advantage group more than the first policy, the second policy/law is preferable – even if it leads to less total wealth than the first.
On a related note, you may find the following article on Hayek v Rawls of interest:
https://www.politics.ox.ac.uk/materials/centres/social-justice/working-papers/SJ017_Lister_MirageofSocialJustice.pdf
> it does not follow that his arguments are wrong
ReplyDeleteI disagree. Refer to his arguments I quote in Utility which are indeed just wrong. I invite you to read my "Consider two societies".